It's not often that NYTimes conservative columnist, David Brooks, finds any way to use science try to justify the lifestyles of the rich and separate, but someone sent him news of a study that he obviously felt he could manipulate to rationalize the continuing resegregation of America and its schools.
What most people know, even those who do not read the results of scientific studies, is that diversity is important for healthy communities, whether business communities concerned with productivity or artistic groups in search of new forms, problem solving groups in search of solutions, or school systems in search of higher achievement for all children.
A clip from TMoE (pp. 37-41) on Coleman's findings almost a half century ago:
Good fences make good neighbors. When ethnic groups clash, we usually try to encourage peace by integrating them. Let them get to know one another or perform a joint activity. This may be the wrong approach. Alex Rutherford, Dion Harmon and others studied ethnically diverse areas and came to a different conclusion. Peace is not the result of integrated coexistence. It is the result of well-defined geographic and political boundaries. For example, Switzerland is an ethnically diverse place, but mountains and lakes clearly define each group’s spot. Even in the former Yugoslavia, amid widespread ethnic violence, peace prevailed where there were clear boundaries.Too bad Brooks did not read to the bottom of the abstract, where he would would have found this:
The theory and the data also show that people who are in fully integrated societies will also successfully live in peace.
A clip from TMoE (pp. 37-41) on Coleman's findings almost a half century ago:
The mandate for the Coleman report came from the Civil Rights Act of 1964, which required a research study be con- ducted within two years of passage to identify where educational resources in public educational institutions were lacking due to “race, color, religion,
or national origin” (Lagemann, 2000, p. 193). Almost
overnight, previous education program evaluation criteria based on resource inputs
shifted
to program outputs
as the mandate for tracking education program
effective- ness was written
into federal legislation.
While everyone,
including James Coleman, expected
to find large dif- ferences
in achievement based on large differences in resources between the 600,000
children that
his
study
included in
4,000
Black and White
schools, the findings confounded expectations. As Coleman scholar, Ger- ald Grant (2009) points out Coleman found discrepancies in spending be- tween Black and White
schools to be less than expected, due to infusions of cash by Southern states in hopes
of maintaining the “separate but equal” apartheid systems. But, even where resource differences were large, Cole- man
found these
disparities
in Black schools
influenced student achieve- ment differences much less than “who
you went to school with”:
Simply put, Coleman found that
the
achievement of both poor and rich children was depressed by
attending a school where
most
children came
from low-income families. More important to the goal of achieving equal ed- ucational opportunity, he found that the achievement of poor children was raised by attending a predominantly middle-class school, while the achieve- ment
of affluent children in the school was not harmed. This was true even if per-pupil
expenditures were the same
at both schools. No research over
the past 40 years has overturned Coleman’s
finding. . . . (p. 159)
Coleman and his team (1966)
found, too, that non-Asian minority chil- dren are more affected by social composition than are White children, and that “if a minority pupil from a home
without
much
educational strength
is put with schoolmates with strong educational backgrounds, his achieve- ment
is likely to increase” (p.
22). Though this finding is commonly
cited in
analyses and interpretations of the Coleman study, the dynamics
that shape this social
fact are most
often
attributed to
the
social capital that accrues
for various
reasons when poor children go
to school with middle class children. Coleman,
however, clearly introduces a race element beyond socioeconomic status that is related to the effects
of oppression and de- moralization that
is rarely cited. Therefore, we
include this rather lengthy quote below, which if
attended to by policy makers,
would doubtless create an added urgency to dust off long-neglected
integration plans. Notice
that Coleman remains loyal to and supportive of the charge given to him under Section
402 of Civil Rights
Act of 1964 to provide data
related to “the lack of equal educational opportunity for individuals
by reason of race,
color, religion, or national origin . . . ,” even though his investigations have led him to findings that even Coleman could not have predicted:
This analysis has concentrated on the educational opportunities offered by the
schools in terms of
the student body composition, facilities, curriculums, and teachers. This emphasis, while
entirely appropriate as a response to the legislation
for the survey, nevertheless neglects important factors in the variability
between individual pupils within the same school:
this variability is roughly four times as large as the variability between schools. For example, a pupil attitude factor, which appears to have a stronger relationship to
achievement than do all the “school” factors
together, is the extent
to which an individual feels that he has some control over his own destiny [italics added]. . . . The responses of pupils, except for
Orientals, have far less conviction
than
Whites that they can affect their own
environments and futures. When they do, however,
their achievement is
higher than that
of Whites who lack that conviction.
Furthermore, while this characteristic shows
little
relationship to
most school
factors, it is related, for Negroes, to the proportion of Whites in the schools. Those Negroes
in schools
with a higher proportion of Whites have a greater sense of control. This finding suggests that the
direction such an attitude takes may be associated with the pupil’s school
experience as well as the
experience in the larger
community. (p. 23)
Coleman found hope, then,
strongly correlated with the presence of a sense of
autonomy, which is more
easily demonstrated, measured, and retained
where racial and economic mixing prevails, rather than in racially and eco- nomically segregated environments—whether that segregation is sustained by antiquated beliefs, legal maneuvering, or by outdated school assessment
practices. And it was this “pupil attitude factor” of hope that had a greater effect on achievement than
all other school effects examined in
the Coleman study, which remains the
largest
research undertaking of its kind in U.S. educational history.
The Coleman findings on socioeconomic status
and
school
achievement echoed the findings
of another large, longitudinal study a few years earlier,
whose similar
results on the topic were
similarly ignored (for similar reasons, we may assume). The federal research
project in 1960, Project Talent, involved detailed questionnaires in over 1,300
high schools and a series of tests
for 440,000 students that included achievement, attitudinal, interest, and aptitude tests, surveys, and questionnaires. Instruments were administered in 1960 when students were ninth graders and
again in 1963 when they were seniors.
By 1973, it is clear that Washington’s elite had digested the implications
of these studies,
as expressed here by fiscal and monetary expert, Alice Rivlin (1973):
The most general result of these
statistical studies
[the Coleman Study and the Project
Talent study] has been the finding that variables reflecting the
socioeconomic characteristics of students and their families explain most
of the variation in test scores,
and variables reflecting school characteristics or
resource inputs explain very little.
These results should not be exaggerated—they
do not prove that
“schools don’t matter”—but they certainly provide a basis for considerable skepti- cism about
using
test
scores
as measures of the output of
the education
industry as such. Test score changes may primarily reflect changes
in the school
population and
the
way it is mixed, rather than the productivity
of school
resources themselves. (p. 424)
Lagemann (2000) recounts the
drama surrounding the
release of the Coleman Report’s initial findings in 1966, and the subsequent “firestorm” set off within
the Johnson Administration, which knew that Coleman’s findings could sabotage the Administration’s strategy of using the federal purse
to buy Southern support
to end apartheid schooling in
the South, as set forth by ESEA the
year before. Johnson knew that Republicans, already resistant to more federal spending, would seize and exploit the counter- intuitive fact
that spending levels were clearly not the prime factor in performance discrepancies. Coleman’s findings, too, offered a swipe at a core component of the American
secular faith in education and educational op- portunity as “the chief instrument for redressing the inequalities of American life” (Kantor, 1991, p. 50).
This lofty notion had, indeed, fed the Jeffersonian belief, later transferred
to Horace Mann, that education
may provide solutions
to social problems that
were thought to
be the result
of the poor’s
own shortcom- ings. Blaming
the
poor
for their poverty is as traditional as
our Calvinist
forefathers of Puritan New England, who viewed the socioeconomically
unfit as having earned their
lack of status through their own moral failings (Rippa, 1996). These shortcomings, in turn, might
signal the column of
the celestial tally sheet
to which
all souls had been added who
were not a part of the Elect,
or God’s elite. From this early theological base, there eventu- ally grew the Protestant economic catechism
of the Gilded
Age, with ample doses
thrown
in of Social Darwinism,
which
“held
that
responsibility for
poverty lay not with the business cycle or the existence
of a capitalist reserve
army of the unemployed, but with the moral
failure of the poor
themselves to conduct proper family economy” (Dawley, 1993, p. 27).
By the 1960s the poor’s personal flaws and the lifestyles they spawned
were bundled within a new and encompassing concept known as the “culture of poverty,” which acknowledged structural barriers as well as the traditional blaming of the victim:7
First, though it acknowledged the structural sources of deprivation, the culture of
poverty thesis tended to focus attention more
on
the
personal characteristics of the poor themselves than on the economic and social con- ditions
that
shaped their
lives (Aaron, 1978, p. 20). Consequently, and
this is the
second
point,
because
it implied that people were poor due to their own
attitudes, behaviors, and life-styles, it suggested
that changing the poor rather than
redistributing income
or creating jobs was the best way to elimi- nate the problem of poverty. (p. 55)
The third characteristic that Kantor (1991)
attributes to the “culture- of-poverty thesis”
was its belief
that, since
the economic and psychological conditions left the poor without the “will and capacity
to attack the sources of
their own
deprivation” (p. 55), professional intervention
was required, which assured a powerful
role
for
the
liberal
public
policy
makers
during
the
1960s. Such interventions,
however, did not disrupt the
underlying assumptions of economic order, systems of privilege, or existing power relations, as initiatives to help the poor focused more on education and
training programs. As noted earlier, these kinds of compensatory solutions
could be provided without
disrupting the
social and economic structures that would have been challenged by
job creation programs or
other
alterations to economic and socio-cultural patterns. The preferred compensatory strategies adopted by liberals
could “compensate for
capitalism’s inevitable flaws and omissions without interfering with its internal workings”
(Kantor quoting Brinkley, 1991, p. 56).
Coleman’s findings, however, were not governed by any of these assumptions. His findings clearly suggest
the need for
structural alterations to the racial and socioeconomic organization
of
schools,
while
clearly pointing to
the limited value of simply adding resources without structural modifications. The initial findings of the Coleman Report, therefore, were appropriately muted by
Johnson’s White
House; the media, with no open controversy to sell copy and with
its accepted narrative wisdom to protect, largely ignored the complete findings when they did appear late in 1966 (Coleman et
al, 1966). Both liberal
and
conservative policy
people, then, read the Coleman Report looking for ideological ammunition, and they found it. Conservatives centrally concerned with cutting costs and conserv- ing the status
quo cherry-picked
Coleman’s findings (Alexander, 1997) to argue that “throwing money”8 at educational problems
couldn’t fix them, while liberals used Coleman’s
findings
related to social capital
and
the importance of
racial and economic mixing to argue for mandatory busing policies to achieve racial balance.
Coleman remained disappointed (Coleman,1972) at the reception of the study, and he remained throughout his life an advocate
for removing all barriers to socioeconomic integration, even as an interim measure toward achieving equity and equality (Kahlenberg, 2001). Kahlenberg (2001) cites Coleman from a rare interview in 1972, in which his claim for the significance of social capital is made unequivocal:
Coleman said that research continued to
show that “a child’s performance, especially a working-class child’s
performance, is
greatly benefited by his going to a
school with children who come from educationally stronger back- grounds.” Coleman declared
flatly: “A child’s learning is
a function more of the characteristics
of his classmates than those
of the teacher.” (p. 62)
How different today’s education reform
agenda might
be if Coleman’s core finding had been acknowledged and taken to heart for its central truth: schools alone can
never consistently close the gaps in achievement that reflect deep differences in
levels of autonomy and privilege, wide disparities in opportunity, deep
veins of racism, and an ongoing and deepening hope gap. How different our
schools might be if we were to take seriously what good research already tells us, or if we as a society were to fund other social
science research with the potential to matter in
the health of our neighbor- hoods and our world. Or, how differently
our
schools and our perception
of schools might be if we were to conceive
of educational improvement as one important component
of a comprehensive commitment to social and economic renewal,
in a way
that acknowledges the
wisdom expressed by Jean Anyon’s (1997) quip: “Attempting to fix inner city schools without fixing the city in which they are embedded is
like trying to clean the air on one side of a screen door” (p.
168).
No comments:
Post a Comment